(the English translation of "Filsafat Makna Wittgenstein" posted on Linguastudia, October 2, 2015)
I. Introduction
Since the dawn of civilization, humans have always sought to give meaning or significance to every aspect of their lives, to their experiences, and to what they perceive through their senses. This endeavor to find meaning is realized through language, which simultaneously serves as a tool for philosophy. Therefore, those who initially utilized meaning to analyze ideas or express experiences through language were philosophers, although later, meaning as an object of study became primarily discussed in semantics.
The development of the history of philosophy itself has been characterized by the clash of ideas among philosophers. In this regard, history indirectly teaches us about the origins of philosophical issues with their various peculiarities, each marked by its respective period. One period reacts to the previous period, either correcting or adding aspects considered important (Mustansyir, 1988:56).
A similar development applies to the effort to examine meaning in language. Philosophers who initially studied it were often countered by subsequent philosophers. More uniquely, there exists a philosopher who analyzed meaning in language during one period and later critiqued or contradicted his own thoughts in another period. This philosopher is Ludwig Wittgenstein.
This academic article discusses the development of Wittgenstein's thoughts in examining meaning. The main problem explored is: what are Wittgenstein's ideas about meaning, and how did they evolve? This issue will be approached by referencing materials that illustrate Wittgenstein's thought process about language, particularly concerning meaning.
II. About Ludwig Wittgenstein
Ludwig Wittgenstein was a philosopher of Jewish descent from Austria. He was born in Vienna on April 26, 1889, as the youngest of eight children. In 1906, Wittgenstein began studying at a technical college in Berlin. Two years later, he continued his technical studies in Manchester, where he conducted research in aeronautical engineering, particularly on jet engines and propellers. Since propeller design required substantial mathematical knowledge, his interest increasingly shifted toward mathematics and the philosophy of mathematics.
In 1911, G. Frege, a mathematician, advised him to study philosophy under Bertrand Russell at the University of Cambridge. There, Wittgenstein began his career as a philosopher. He later became renowned as a prominent professor of philosophy at the university, although he resigned from his professorship in 1947. Wittgenstein's two most recognized works are Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and Philosophical Investigations. On April 29, 1951, he died of cancer in Cambridge after two years of illness (Bertens, 2001:41-43).
III. Wittgenstein's First Period: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
Being a student and friend of Bertrand Russell led Wittgenstein to follow the philosophical tradition of Russell’s analytic philosophy. Russell was particularly famous for his theory of logical atomism, which significantly influenced Wittgenstein's first major work, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
a. Russell’s Logical Atomism
Before delving deeper into Tractatus, it is essential to discuss Russell's logical atomism. There are three primary philosophical objectives of Russell's logical atomism (Hidayat, 2009:48):
- Philosophy aims to reduce all knowledge to the most concise and simple language. This goal is to formulate a view that eventually synthesizes ideas.
- Philosophy must connect logic and mathematics. For Russell, all mathematics can be reduced to a few logical principles. He advocated against separating exact sciences and the humanities in education, emphasizing the importance of logic and grammar as fundamental to both language and mathematics.
- Philosophy must refer to linguistic analysis. This is the pinnacle of Russell’s philosophy: to seek true knowledge through proper analysis.
In essence, all of Russell's philosophy revolves around logical language. He believed logical language greatly aids linguistic analysis, asserting that techniques based on logical language better reflect the relationship between language structure and reality structure.
Russell's analytic philosophy and theory of logical atomism significantly influenced Wittgenstein's first major work, despite slight differences in their approaches.
b. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: Meaning is Picture
Initially, Tractatus was Wittgenstein's German manuscript titled Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlungen, published in the journal Annalen der Naturphilosophie (1921). Written during World War I—while Wittgenstein was stationed at the Eastern and Southern fronts and even while imprisoned by the Italian army—it was later published in 1922 as a bilingual book in German and English, titled Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlungen and Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Wibowo, 2011:21).
The work opens with a preface by Bertrand Russell himself, wherein Wittgenstein immediately critiques everyday language—opposing logical language—which he saw as a cause of philosophical confusion among his predecessors:
"In ordinary language, the same word often has different meanings, which apply to different symbols… Consequently, fundamental confusion easily arises in the entire philosophy."
(Wittgenstein, 1922:35-36)
For Wittgenstein, the confusion in philosophical language arises from philosophers’ arbitrary use of language, ignoring the rules of thought as shown in logic (Mustansyir, 1988:62).
"Most propositions and questions posed about philosophical problems are not false but nonsensical. Hence, we cannot answer such questions but only reveal their nonsensicality. Most philosophical questions and propositions arise from our lack of understanding of the logic of our language."
(Wittgenstein, 1922:39)
As a solution, Wittgenstein proposed his first philosophical theory of meaning: "meaning is picture." The essence of this theory is the idea that there is an absolute and close relationship between language (the symbolic world) and the factual world outside of language.
Language acquires meaning only when used to depict factual states of affairs. Wittgenstein concluded that all language could be formulated into a perfect logical language (Hidayat, 2009:73).
IV. Wittgenstein’s Second Period: Philosophical Investigations
After completing Tractatus, Wittgenstein considered that his work had solved all philosophical problems related to meaning. However, after several years away from philosophical writing and reflection, he began to criticize his earlier views and started developing a new perspective on language and meaning.
In his later period, Wittgenstein expressed these criticisms and new ideas in his second major work, Philosophical Investigations. This book was published posthumously in 1953, two years after his death.
a. Criticism of Tractatus
Wittgenstein criticized his earlier notion that meaning is a direct correlation between language and the world, as proposed in Tractatus. He found that this view oversimplified the complexity of language. According to Wittgenstein in his later period, meaning is not just a rigid connection to reality but something shaped by how language is used in various contexts.
"The meaning of a word is its use in the language."
(Wittgenstein, 1953: §43)
With this statement, Wittgenstein introduced the idea that the meaning of words arises from their usage within specific "language games."
b. Language Games and Forms of Life
The concept of language games is central to Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. He argued that language is not a singular system with fixed rules but consists of many "games" with their own rules, depending on the context of their use. Examples include giving orders, making requests, describing events, and storytelling.
For Wittgenstein, language games are diverse, and the rules governing them depend on their purpose and context. This understanding led him to reject the idea of a perfect, logical language as proposed in Tractatus.
Language games are deeply rooted in "forms of life"—the cultural and social contexts within which people use language. In this sense, language cannot be divorced from the everyday practices and activities of human life.
c. Private Language Argument
One of Wittgenstein's most famous arguments in Philosophical Investigations is the private language argument. He challenged the idea that language could be entirely private, existing only in the mind of an individual.
Wittgenstein argued that language is inherently social and depends on shared practices and public criteria. A private language, known only to a single individual, would lack the external standards needed to determine meaning and would, therefore, be nonsensical.
d. Meaning as Use
In his later philosophy, Wittgenstein emphasized the practical and functional aspects of language. He argued that meaning is not something abstract or fixed but emerges from how words are used in real-life situations.
This shift from a rigid, logical view of language to a more flexible, usage-based understanding marked a significant departure from his earlier views in Tractatus.
V. Conclusion
The evolution of Wittgenstein’s thought reflects his journey from a rigid, logical view of language to a more practical, contextual understanding. In his first period, represented by Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Wittgenstein viewed language as a picture of reality, where meaning arises from a direct correspondence between words and facts.
However, in his later period, as expressed in Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein rejected this view and developed a new perspective: meaning is determined by use, and language is shaped by the various "games" people play in their everyday lives.
The shift in Wittgenstein’s philosophy highlights the complexity of language and its deep connection to human activities and social contexts. His contributions remain influential in both philosophy and linguistics, offering valuable insights into the nature of meaning and communication.
Bibliography
Allan, Keith. 1986. Linguistic Meaning (Volume One). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Bertens, K. 2002. Filsafat Barat Kontemporer: Inggris-Jerman. Jakarta: Gramedia.
Hadiwijono, Harun, Dr. Sari Sejarah Filsafat Barat 1. Yogyakarta: Penerbit Kanisius.
Hidayat, Asep Ahmad. 2009. Filsafat Bahasa: Mengungkap Hakikat Bahasa, Makna dan Tanda. Bandung: PT. Remaja Rosdakarya.
Mustansyir, Rizal, Drs. 1988. Filsafat Bahasa: Aneka Masalah Arti dan Upaya Pemecahannya. Jakarta: PT. Prima Karya.
Strawson, P.F. 1969. “Meaning and Truth” dalam Martinich, A.P. (ed.). 1996. The Philosophy of Language (Third Edition). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wibowo, Wahyu, Dr. 2011. Linguistik Fenomenologis John Langshaw Austin: Ketika Tuturan Berarti Tindakan. Jakarta: Bidik-Phronesis Publishing.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., Ltd.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical Investigations (trans.: G.E.M. Anscombe). Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd.